2012
DOI: 10.1007/s12136-011-0138-9
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Empirical Negation

Abstract: An extension of intuitionism to empirical discourse, a project most seriously taken up by Dummett and Tennant, requires an empirical negation whose strength lies somewhere between classical negation ('It is unwarranted that. . . ') and intuitionistic negation ('It is refutable that. . . '). I put forward one plausible candidate that compares favorably to some others that have been propounded in the literature. A tableau calculus is presented and shown to be strongly complete.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
27
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
2

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 14 publications
(27 citation statements)
references
References 21 publications
0
27
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Changing perspective, from an intuitionistic viewpoint there is a certain advantage in considering Beth semantics. There is a relatively simple proof of intuitionistic completeness (proving completeness with only intuitionistically accepted principles) for intuitionistic logic [3,11]. The intuitionistic completeness proof for Kripke semantics [12] gives a more refined result, but is comparatively more involved.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Changing perspective, from an intuitionistic viewpoint there is a certain advantage in considering Beth semantics. There is a relatively simple proof of intuitionistic completeness (proving completeness with only intuitionistically accepted principles) for intuitionistic logic [3,11]. The intuitionistic completeness proof for Kripke semantics [12] gives a more refined result, but is comparatively more involved.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In the first paper, we semantically investigated how some logics with nonstandard negation (IPC ∼ [1,2], TCC ω [4], daC [9] and CC ω [10]) are related to each other. In particular, we noted how the difference between IPC ∼ and TCC ω can be understood as the difference between Kripke and Beth semantics.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…We shall observe that this difference in rules can be eliminated, by replacing [RP] with [RC] and an additional axiom. This will give a completeness proof of daC with respect to the semantics of CC ω , and thus the semantics of Došen [5]. It will also provide a more unified viewpoint of the logics related to CC ω as defined by extra axioms with no change in rules.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 89%
“…8 In logics without this restriction, such as classical logic, this fails by contraction, so there may exist a disjunction α ∨ β without any means of deciding which formula is proved, which is problematic if we pursue a semantics of proof. …”
Section: Proof-theoretic Semanticsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…7 Furthermore, as Shramko et al [40] point out, if we define falsity in terms of negation, then we are led to a reliance, not only on a syntactic feature (negation), but also on truth, and, as Dummett [10] is aware, this, leads to bivalence under commonly-held assumptions regarding the nature of proofs [see author reference omitted for discussion]. 8 To get ahead of ourselves, this property is mirrored in co-intuitionistic logic by the "conjunction property", where α ∧ β iff α or β. 9 Lafont [14, Appendix B.1] argues that 'classical logic is inconsistent, not from a logical viewpoint (false is not provable), but from an algorithmic one', since proofs can not be considered algorithmically, and so 'classical logic has no denotational semantics, except the trivial one which identifies all the proofs of the same type'.…”
Section: Bi-intuitionismmentioning
confidence: 99%