2010
DOI: 10.1086/650206
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Epistemic Values and the Argument from Inductive Risk

Abstract: JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.. The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
3
1
1

Citation Types

0
96
0
3

Year Published

2013
2013
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
4
4

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 154 publications
(99 citation statements)
references
References 36 publications
0
96
0
3
Order By: Relevance
“…Steel argues that it should be possible to amend the standards of evidence by the presence of risk (risk avoidance is a non-epistemic value) [63]. I think it is important, however, not to compromise our wish to satisfy the epistemic curiosity when we set the standards aimed at satisfying our prudential curiosity.…”
Section: How Certain Do We Need To Be? a Question Of Ethics As Well Amentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Steel argues that it should be possible to amend the standards of evidence by the presence of risk (risk avoidance is a non-epistemic value) [63]. I think it is important, however, not to compromise our wish to satisfy the epistemic curiosity when we set the standards aimed at satisfying our prudential curiosity.…”
Section: How Certain Do We Need To Be? a Question Of Ethics As Well Amentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In philosophy of science, the normative question has been the most controversial one (Steel 2010). As an example, Laudan (1984) points out that the validation of scientific knowledge must not be subject to any non-cognitive values.…”
Section: Values In Sciencementioning
confidence: 99%
“…2 Value-related debates underlie most of the current controversies with respect to the role of scientific knowledge in the evaluation and management of scientific and technological risks (Murphy et al 2006;Lacey 2005;Douglas 2000;Shrader-Frechette 2001, 2004aCranor 1993Cranor , 2011Steel 2011;Betz 2013;Mayo and Spanos 2006;Elliot and McKaughan 2009). What makes this issue even more pertinent from a philosophical standpoint is that in many senses science, at least when applied to decision making, appears not to be compatible with the traditional ideal of value-free science (Steel 2010(Steel , 2015Elliot and McKaughan 2009;Shrader-Frechette 1994;Cranor 1997;Douglas 2009). …”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Place has been most extensively developed by geographers of science, whose efforts have contributed to a disciplinary 'spatial turn' in the history and philosophy of science (Finnegan 2008;Livingstone 2010;Naylor 2005), which has prompted a re-evaluation of the laboratory as a singularly important kind of place (Gooday 2008). Epistemic values have become increasingly important in the history and philosophy of science (along with epistemic goals), as scientific research programmes that deal with social, environmental, and industrial issues have become more central (Elliott 2011;Steel 2010). Practices meanwhile have been at the heart of some of our most innovative histories and philosophies of experiment (Chang 2012;Rheinberger 1997), though in such cases the emphasis on laboratory practice makes them exceedingly difficult to extend to the field.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%