2016
DOI: 10.1002/9781118947074.ch2
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Evidence and Epistemic Causality

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
5

Relationship

1
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 7 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 16 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…This appendix sketches some motivation for epistemic causality and compares epistemic causality to some other theories of causality. For further discussion of the epistemic theory of causality, see Williamson (2005Williamson ( , 2006aWilliamson ( , b, 2013, Russo and Williamson (2007), Wilde and Williamson (2016).…”
Section: Appendix: Motivation and Relation To Other Theories Of Causamentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This appendix sketches some motivation for epistemic causality and compares epistemic causality to some other theories of causality. For further discussion of the epistemic theory of causality, see Williamson (2005Williamson ( , 2006aWilliamson ( , b, 2013, Russo and Williamson (2007), Wilde and Williamson (2016).…”
Section: Appendix: Motivation and Relation To Other Theories Of Causamentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Of the three main requirements of his objective Bayesianism (probability, calibration and equivocation), upholding the norm of equivocation (which asks that one's degrees of belief should equivocate as far as possible between the elementary outcomes; Russo and Williamson 2007: 168), amounts to introducing a classical explanatory constraint, namely simplicity and parsimony. This can be seen by looking at the corresponding account of epistemic causation developed by Williamson. On this account, the norm of equivocation asks that a causal graph be as non-committal as possible about what causes what: 'A causal graph C is maximally non-committal, from all those in E, if there is no other causal graph D in E which makes fewer causal claims (including both arrows and gaps) than C' (Wilde and Williamson 2016). Williamson's objective Bayesianism leaves enough room to introduce other explanatory elements, and we will shortly come back to his insightful relationship between causation and Bayesianism.…”
Section: State Of the Artthe Relationship And Compatibility Between Imentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This can be seen by looking at the corresponding account of epistemic causation developed by Williamson. On this account, the norm of equivocation asks that a causal graph be as non-committal as possible about what causes what: ‘A causal graph C is maximally non-committal, from all those in E, if there is no other causal graph D in E which makes fewer causal claims (including both arrows and gaps) than C’ (Wilde and Williamson 2016). Williamson's objective Bayesianism leaves enough room to introduce other explanatory elements, and we will shortly come back to his insightful relationship between causation and Bayesianism.…”
Section: State Of the Art – The Relationship And Compatibility Betweementioning
confidence: 99%