2009
DOI: 10.1016/j.actpsy.2009.07.005
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Indicative and counterfactual ‘only if’ conditionals

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
2
1

Citation Types

0
8
0

Year Published

2010
2010
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
9
1

Relationship

4
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 19 publications
(8 citation statements)
references
References 48 publications
0
8
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In order to account for these two main empirical results, we have proposed an explanation that combines some aspects of other studies (Carriedo, García-Madruga, Moreno, & Gutiérrez, 1999;Egan, Byrne, & García-Madruga, 2007;García-Madruga, Gutiérrez, Carriedo, Moreno, & Johnson-Laird, 2002;García-Madruga, Moreno, Quelhas & Juhos, 2007). This proposal suggests that reasoners understand only if by thinking about two possibilities or models, as proposed by Johnson-Laird and Byrne (1991), but in the directional way proposed by .…”
Section: Conditional Reasoning and Mental Model Theorymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In order to account for these two main empirical results, we have proposed an explanation that combines some aspects of other studies (Carriedo, García-Madruga, Moreno, & Gutiérrez, 1999;Egan, Byrne, & García-Madruga, 2007;García-Madruga, Gutiérrez, Carriedo, Moreno, & Johnson-Laird, 2002;García-Madruga, Moreno, Quelhas & Juhos, 2007). This proposal suggests that reasoners understand only if by thinking about two possibilities or models, as proposed by Johnson-Laird and Byrne (1991), but in the directional way proposed by .…”
Section: Conditional Reasoning and Mental Model Theorymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…People make more inferences that require access to “there were no oranges and no pears” from the counterfactual compared to the factual indicative conditional, such as modus tollens (from “there were no pears” to “therefore there were no oranges”). But they also make the same frequency of inferences that require access to “there were oranges and pears” from both conditionals, such as modus ponens – from “there were oranges” to “therefore there were pears” (e.g., Byrne and Tasso, 1999; Thompson and Byrne, 2002; see also Moreno-Ríos et al, 2008; Egan et al, 2009). They do so for various different sorts of content (e.g., Frosch and Byrne, 2012; see also Quelhas and Byrne, 2003; Egan and Byrne, 2012).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 94%
“…The willingness of participants to make inferences such as modus ponens and modus tollens from counterfactuals has been examined not only for basic concrete content, such as conditionals about people in places (e.g., Byrne & Tasso, ) but also for other sorts of content, such as causal and definitional counterfactuals (e.g., Frosch & Byrne, ; Thompson & Byrne, ), and deontic and inducement counterfactuals (e.g., Egan & Byrne, ; Quelhas & Byrne, ). They make such inferences for counterfactuals based on various linguistic forms including “there would have been roses only if there had been orange trees” and “ even if there had been roses there would have been orange trees” (e.g., Egan, Garcia‐Madruga, & Byrne, ; Moreno‐Rios, Garcia‐Madruga, & Byrne, ). The dual meaning of counterfactuals has been examined for counterfactuals about the past, and also subjunctive conditionals about the present, and pre‐factual conditionals about the future (e.g., Byrne & Egan, ; Byrne & Tasso, ).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%