2002
DOI: 10.1080/13546780244000079
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Linguistic-pragmatic factors in interpreting disjunctions

Abstract: The connective or can be treated as an inclusive disjunction or else as an exclusive disjunction. Although researchers are aware of this distinction, few have examined the conditions under which each interpretation should be anticipated. Based on linguistic-pragmatic analyses, we assume that interpretations are initially inclusive before either (a) remaining so, or (b) becoming exclusive by way of an implicature (but not both). We point to a class of situations that ought to predispose disjunctions to inclusiv… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

2
30
0

Year Published

2003
2003
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
7
3

Relationship

2
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 61 publications
(32 citation statements)
references
References 22 publications
2
30
0
Order By: Relevance
“…For example, the linguistic literature has pointed out how Negative Polarity items work. 3 When a speaker says, e.g., I did not eat ice cream, it automatically entails that he did not eat chocolate ice cream either (see Noveck, Chierchia, Chevaux, Guelminger, & Sylvestre, 2002). If the primary role of negation were to point to things he ate instead, then it would be hard to see how negations could so readily license further inferences like these.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 97%
“…For example, the linguistic literature has pointed out how Negative Polarity items work. 3 When a speaker says, e.g., I did not eat ice cream, it automatically entails that he did not eat chocolate ice cream either (see Noveck, Chierchia, Chevaux, Guelminger, & Sylvestre, 2002). If the primary role of negation were to point to things he ate instead, then it would be hard to see how negations could so readily license further inferences like these.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 97%
“…A strong default approach has been defended by Neo-Griceans like Levinson (2000) and to some extent by Horn (1984, p. 13). More recently, Chierchia (2004) and Chierchia, Crain, Guasti, Gualmini, and Meroni (2001) have essentially defended the strong default view by making a syntactic distinction with respect to scalar terms: when a scalar is embedded in a downward-entailing context (e.g., negations and question forms), Chierchia and colleagues predict that one would not find the production of scalar inferences (also see Noveck, Chierchia, Chevaux, Guelminger, & Sylvestre, 2002). Otherwise, Chierchia and colleagues do assume that scalar inferences go through.…”
Section: Scalar Inferences Are Examples Of What Paulmentioning
confidence: 97%
“…Nothing prevents an exclusive interpretation for such disjunctions -a fact that has led to controversy about the basic meaning of disjunctions (cf. Fillenbaum, 1974;Newstead, Griggs, & Chrostowski, 1984;Chierchia et al, 2001;Noveck et al, 2002;Chevallier et al, 2008; and for a review, Johnson-Laird et al, 2012). The forwards and backwards disjunctions were evidently a little confusing -they are perhaps pragmatically odd without an appropriate context, because they seem redundant (cf.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%