2019
DOI: 10.3389/fpsyg.2019.00189
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Linking Hypothesis and Number of Response Options Modulate Inferred Scalar Implicature Rate

Abstract: The past 15 years have seen increasing experimental investigations of core pragmatic questions in the ever more active and lively field of experimental pragmatics. Within experimental pragmatics, many of the core questions have relied on the operationalization of the theoretical notion of “implicature rate.” Implicature rate based results have informed the work on acquisition, online processing, and scalar diversity, inter alia. Implicature rate has typically been quantified as the proportion of “pragmatic” ju… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
23
0

Year Published

2021
2021
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 21 publications
(24 citation statements)
references
References 48 publications
1
23
0
Order By: Relevance
“…However, if a third intermediate option is provided, participants may opt to also express the incompleteness or infelicity of a guess in the task -depending on the label of the intermediate option. In a followup study, we found that participants opt for the intermediate option more often if it is labeled as "kinda right" rather than "neither" (Jasbi et al, 2019). Most importantly, children may differ from adults in how they approach intermediate judgments in forced choice tasks.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 77%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…However, if a third intermediate option is provided, participants may opt to also express the incompleteness or infelicity of a guess in the task -depending on the label of the intermediate option. In a followup study, we found that participants opt for the intermediate option more often if it is labeled as "kinda right" rather than "neither" (Jasbi et al, 2019). Most importantly, children may differ from adults in how they approach intermediate judgments in forced choice tasks.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 77%
“…There are many possible labels for the middle option on a scale, including "kinda right", "kinda wrong", or "neither". A later experiment, tested different intermediate labels and found that adults consider "kinda right" to be a more suitable option for capturing pragmatic infelicities (see Jasbi et al, 2019). We expect similar behavior from labels that refer to non-maximal degrees of being "right" such as "a bit right" or "a little right".…”
Section: Participantsmentioning
confidence: 85%
“…Participants' task was to judge to what extent the sentence matches the picture: to what degree the sentence gives a true description of the depicted scenario. A ternary scale was employed (Figure 1) because it has been shown to be more adequate than the binary choice to detect sensitivity to false implicit meanings (Katsos & Bishop, 2011) and deviations from complete truth in the case of partially correct descriptions more generally (Jasbi et al, 2019).…”
Section: Methodsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…To connect our model's predictions with the available truth-value judgment data in the descriptive truth-value judgment tasks described above, we follow recent suggestions in the literature for how to treat truth-value judgments. In particular, truth-value judgments are not viewed as pure language comprehension behavior, but rather as a form of language production (e.g., Degen & Goodman 2014;Jasbi et al 2019). Recall from our discussion of the task above that it does not present as a typical comprehension task because both the participant and the speaker in the particular truth-value judgment tasks we model are already aware of the true world state.…”
Section: A Computational Cognitive Model For Every-not Utterancesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…To model the utterance endorsement implicit in truth-value judgment behavior, we need one more level of inference. As mentioned above, we follow Degen & Goodman (2014) and Jasbi et al (2019) in modeling descriptive truth-value judgment data as speaker production behavior, which means we need to generate predictions from a speaker layer in our model. However, S 1 is not a reasonable model of a human speaker in the task because S 1 jointly observes the world state, the intended scope interpretation, and the intended QUD; human participants observe only the world state (e.g., the number of horses who jumped).…”
Section: Utility)mentioning
confidence: 99%