1997
DOI: 10.1016/s0378-2166(96)00081-1
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Some telling examples: A reply to Tsohatzidis

Abstract: (1978) and Zeno Vendler (1980) have independently claimed that tell behaves in two different ways, depending on its complement. When it is used with a whcomplement, as in (1) The boy told them where he had spent the night it requires that the subject spoke the truth: (1) could only be correctly used if the boy had spoken truthfully. In contrast, when tell is used with a that-complement, as in (2) The boy told them that he had spent the night with friends it brings no such requirement; (2) could be used corre… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
63
0
1

Year Published

2008
2008
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
7
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 46 publications
(64 citation statements)
references
References 3 publications
0
63
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…Known as "factivity," this property of the verb "know" is not shared by verbs such as "think," which are classified as nonfactive: it is fully acceptable to say "John thinks that the door is locked, but the door isn't locked." However, we can also use the verb "to know" in a projected or non-literal sense, as in the sentence "John knew that his team was going to win, and then they didn't" (Holton, 1997). Someone who asserts this sentence is best understood as expressing the thought that it seemed very much to John that he knew.…”
Section: Prevalence and Universality Of Epistemic Intuitions Regardinmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Known as "factivity," this property of the verb "know" is not shared by verbs such as "think," which are classified as nonfactive: it is fully acceptable to say "John thinks that the door is locked, but the door isn't locked." However, we can also use the verb "to know" in a projected or non-literal sense, as in the sentence "John knew that his team was going to win, and then they didn't" (Holton, 1997). Someone who asserts this sentence is best understood as expressing the thought that it seemed very much to John that he knew.…”
Section: Prevalence and Universality Of Epistemic Intuitions Regardinmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…To begin, the special emphasis on 'knew' in that remark is plausibly a clue that 'knew' is not being used in a straightforward fashion. Richard Holton argues that such utterances gain their dramatic flair from 'protagonist projection', in which one puts oneself in the position of another (or in this case, one's past self), deliberately selecting words fitting that perspective rather than our current one (Holton, 1997). Note that one could say to similar effect, "Up until the last chapter, the butler was obviously the murderer, and then it turned out he wasn't."…”
Section: What the Two Disciplines Mean By 'Mental States' And 'Knowlementioning
confidence: 99%
“…The first of these, originally put forward by Austin 1954, concerns the opposition between why-and how-questions. Questions concerning the justification of belief are typically why-questions, while questions concerning the justification of knowledge are typically how-questions: (17) a (20), however. 5 None of these contrasts, we should note, provides clear linguistic evidence for the idea that "that"-clauses are ambiguous.…”
Section: Facts and Propositions (Ginzburg 1995)mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…For instance, in order to have a belief about who came, it is probably sufficient to believe a proposition that only partially answers the question (rather than a potential complete answer in GS's sense). 17 For a verb like agree, on the other hand, the meaning assumed seems adequate, since in order to agree about who left, it is not enough to agree on some partial answer: John and Mary may agree that Sue left, bit disagree about Janet, for instance, in which case they disagree about who left.…”
Section: Agree Be Certain and The Role Of Prepositionsmentioning
confidence: 99%