2019
DOI: 10.1007/s42113-019-0025-9
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Testing Optimal Timing in Value-Linked Decision Making

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

3
16
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 18 publications
(19 citation statements)
references
References 74 publications
3
16
0
Order By: Relevance
“…We …nd that View clicks are decreasing in the length of the longest line but Implicit response times are increasing in the length of the longest line. Additionally, we …nd that View clicks are increasing across trials but Implicit response times are decreasing across trials.3 3 SeeHenmon (1911),Kellogg (1931),Bhui (2019b), andDu¤y and Smith (2020).…”
mentioning
confidence: 74%
“…We …nd that View clicks are decreasing in the length of the longest line but Implicit response times are increasing in the length of the longest line. Additionally, we …nd that View clicks are increasing across trials but Implicit response times are decreasing across trials.3 3 SeeHenmon (1911),Kellogg (1931),Bhui (2019b), andDu¤y and Smith (2020).…”
mentioning
confidence: 74%
“…Interestingly, the theoretically optimal policy for the binary decision case ( Tajima et al, 2016 ) is inconsistent with empirical observations of magnitude-sensitive reaction-times ( Teodorescu et al ( 2016 ); Pirrone et al ( 2018a ); Steverson et al ( 2019 ); Zajkowski et al ( 2019 ); Turner et al ( 2019 ), but see Bhui ( 2019 )), unless assumptions are made that subjective utilities for decision-makers are nonlinear, or decisions are embedded in a fixed-length time period with known or learnable distributions of trial option values, so that a variable opportunity cost arises from decision time ( Tajima et al, 2016 ). Furthermore, even single-trial dynamics lead to magnitude sensitive reaction times ( Pirrone et al, 2018b ).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 83%
“…We are not the …rst authors to study choice in a setting where material outcomes depend on imperfectly perceived objects with objectively measurable properties. For instance, researchers have made payments to subjects as a function of judgments involving the relative quantity of dots (Caplin and Dean, 2015;Dutilh and Rieskamp, 2016), the dominant direction of moving dots (Bhui, 2019a;2019b), the number of ‡ickering dots (Oud et al, 2016), a dynamic display of dots (Zeigenfuse, Pleskac, and Liu, 2014), the heights of bars of dynamic size (Tsetsos et al, 2016), and the area occupied by objects of various sizes (Polanía, Krajbich, Grueschow, and Ru¤, 2014). 5 To our knowledge, Du¤y, Gussman, and Smith (2019) is the only other paper that describes a choice experiment where suboptimal choices are perfectly observable because utility Saito, and Tserenjigmid (2018), Koida (2018), Kovach and Tserenjigmid (2018), Caplin, Dean, and Leahy (2019), Cattaneo, Ma, Masatlioglu, and Suleymanov (2019), Conte and Hey (2019), and Natenzon (2019).…”
Section: Choice Involving Imperfectly Perceived Objectsmentioning
confidence: 99%