According to the fitting-attitudes account of value, for X to be good is for it to be fitting to value X. But what is it for an attitude to be fitting? A popular recent view is that it is for there to be sufficient reason for the attitude. In this paper we argue that proponents of the fitting-attitudes account should reject this view and instead take fittingness as basic. In this way they avoid the notorious 'wrong kind of reason' problem, and can offer attractive accounts of reasons and good reasoning in terms of fittingness.According to the fitting-attitudes account of value, what it is for X to be good is for it to be fitting to value X. Famously proposed by Brentano and Ewing, the fitting-attitudes account takes goodness to be similar to properties like that of being admirable, fearful, or amusing. 1 These properties are plausibly understood as a matter of the fittingness or appropriateness of a certain human response: admiration, fear, or amusement. Similarly, on the fitting-attitudes view, goodness, or being valuable, is a matter of the fittingness of the response of valuing.The fitting-attitudes account is often thought to constitute an attractive middle-ground between subjectivist views on which something is good just if we value it and Moorean views * For very helpful comments on earlier versions of this paper, we would like to thank Richard Chappell, Guy 2 on which goodness is a basic, non-natural -and, so critics say, mysterious -property. And while the advantages of the fitting-attitudes account over Moorean views should not be overstated -the metaphysical questions that arise about Moorean goodness seem also to arise about fittingness -the connection between value and human valuing responses does seem an attractive feature of the fitting-attitudes account.Nonetheless, and even putting aside the question of whether fittingness is a 'nonnatural' property, there is an important question about how fittingness is to be understood. A popular recent suggestion is that fittingness should be understood in terms of reasons -roughly, that what it is for it to be fitting to value X is for there to be sufficient reason to value X. This idea is especially natural for those sympathetic to the recently influential reasons-first approach to normativity. On this approach, reasons are the basic normative unit, and the rest of the normative and evaluative domain can be understood in terms of reasons. 2 If we put this view together with the fitting-attitudes account, we reach the buck-passing account of value: what it is for X to be good is for there to be sufficient reason to value X.The aim of this paper is to argue that proponents of the fitting-attitudes account should not take this path. Instead, they should take fittingness as basic. Doing so results in a view which has all the attractions of the buck-passing view, and more, but avoids a serious problem facing the buck-passer. In making this case, we also show how reasons (and thus oughts) can be understood in terms of fittingness. The paper thus makes ...