2015
DOI: 10.1007/s11229-015-0704-6
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The feeling of agency hypothesis: a critique

Abstract: A dominant view in contemporary cognitive neuroscience is that low-level, comparator-based mechanisms of motor control produce a distinctive experience often called the feeling of agency (the FoA-hypothesis). An opposing view is that comparator-based motor control is largely non-conscious and not associated with any particular type of distinctive phenomenology (the simple hypothesis). In this paper, I critically evaluate the nature of the empirical evidence researchers commonly take to support FoA-hypothesis. … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
17
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 18 publications
(17 citation statements)
references
References 60 publications
0
17
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Another example of the thetic approach is Grünbaum's (2015) argument that what subjects report (or experimenters interpret) as a feeling of agency, may ultimately be reducible to the awareness for one's conscious intentions (possibly based on premotor processes involving intentions, planning and action-selection), and therefore not a distinct kind of agency experience after all. In this respect we note that by considering only the case of an Bintention-free^feeling of agency (ibid., p. 21), the author implicitly rules out the possibility that the experience of agency may be distinct in virtue not of its irreducibility to conscious intentions, but of its being implicit in the first-personal givenness or egocentricity of (motor-)intentional actions; which we have here spelled out as the reaffirmation of a sensorimotor system's agency in intentional action.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Another example of the thetic approach is Grünbaum's (2015) argument that what subjects report (or experimenters interpret) as a feeling of agency, may ultimately be reducible to the awareness for one's conscious intentions (possibly based on premotor processes involving intentions, planning and action-selection), and therefore not a distinct kind of agency experience after all. In this respect we note that by considering only the case of an Bintention-free^feeling of agency (ibid., p. 21), the author implicitly rules out the possibility that the experience of agency may be distinct in virtue not of its irreducibility to conscious intentions, but of its being implicit in the first-personal givenness or egocentricity of (motor-)intentional actions; which we have here spelled out as the reaffirmation of a sensorimotor system's agency in intentional action.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…First, nothing equivalent to the “pre‐reflective sense of agency” postulated in the previous model features in this alternative model. The new model is neutral as to whether or not such a thing exists (though see Grünbaum, 2015; Paglieri, 2013); it just implies that temporal binding can be explained without appealing to this notion. Secondly, the variable assumed to underlie binding in this new model is a belief in a causal relation between the two events that are bound together, rather than anything specifically to do with agency as such (though we will shortly return to ways in which agency might nevertheless be relevant to binding on this model, too).…”
Section: Toward An Alternative Conceptualization Of Temporal Bindingmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Without describing all of the arguments of these authors, it is clear that a single comparator mechanism cannot fully account for all aspect of SoA, in particular, a simple comparison between the predicted and actual sensory feedback is not a satisfactory model of broad SoA (see Grünbaum, 2015). More evidence is needed to decide whether a single comparison is a correct model of narrow SoA.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%