The Baire number of the real line (see 1.1(c)) has uncountable cofinality [Mi]. This number is equal to the Baire number of the space 2ω and also to the Baire number (1.1(d)) of every countable partial order. Our research is motivated by the following open question (1.13) (see also [BPS] and [Mi]): can the cofinality of nκ, the Baire number of the space (2κ)κ (1.1(b)), be less than or equal to κ? This question is nontrivial when κ is regular and 2κ = κ (1.3). A. Miller proved that the answer is “no” if κ is strongly inaccessible (see [Mi] and 1.11). Assuming CH, is equal to the Baire number of the Stone space of ℘(ω)/Fin.In §1 we discuss , the Baire number of the space (2λ)κ. If κ is regular, then , and using 1.3 and 1.5, we may rule out the easy cases and restrict ourselves to cases where κ is regular with 2<κ = κ, and κ ≤ λ 2κ. If λ > κ, then it is consistent to have cof()=κ ([Mi] and 1.7). We do not know whether is consistent (1.9). Next, the cardinal number eκ is defined (1.10). It is easy to see that nκ ≤ eκ and that cof(eκ) > κ. If κ is strongly inaccessible (s.i.), then nκ = eκ ([Mil], [Bar], [MF] and 1.11). For κ accessible, the question of whether nκ = eκ is open.Another open question (Fremlin) is stated as follows: assume W ⊇ V and f ∈ ωω ∩ W is such that, for every g ∈ ω ω ∩ V, ∣(f = g)∣ = ℵ0, does this imply that W contains sets which are ω-Cohen (1.1(a)) over V? If κ is accessible regular with 2<κ = κ, then the answer to the analog of Fremlin's question for κ is “no”. In fact, any κ-closed forcing that adds new subsets of κ, also adds a new function f ∈ κκ such that, for every g ∈ κκ ∩V, (f = g) is stationary (4.1(a)). On the other hand, perfect-set forcing on κ (see [Ka] and §5) adds a new subset of κ but produces a minimal extension (5.4(b)), and hence adds no sets which are κ-Cohen over V.
Let be the least cardinal θ such that MAθ fails, (i.e. MA) implies that is regular. Models for regular with are easy to get (see [Ku1]). Fremlin and Miller proved that cof() > ω [Fr, 41C(d)]. The question of whether it is consistent that be singular was solved, in the affirmative, by Kunen [Ku1]. Kunen used a (θ, θ) strong gap in (ω)/Fin, whose splitting partial order is c.c.c. He showed that if cof(θ) = ω1, and P is a c.c.c. partial order of cardinality < θ that may destroy the strong gap, then there exists another c.c.c. partial order Q, which does not destroy the strong gap, and such that ⊩Q “P is not c.c.c”. One then gets Kunen's model by iterating c.c.c. partial orders of cardinality < θ, without destroying the strong (θ, θ) gap. It is unknown whether it is consistent to have ω1 < cof() < .Clearly, there exists a c.c.c. partial order Q with ∣Q∣ = , such that (Q) = (see (1.1)). A partial order P is σ-centered iff P is the union of countably many centered subsets, where a subset A ⊆ P is centered iff p ≤ q. Clearly, a σ-centered partial order is c.c.c. Bell and Szymański proved that (σ-centered) is regular (see [Be] or [Fr, 14C], and [Fr, 21K] or [vD, 3.1(e)]). This implies that if P is a σ-centered partial order, and is singular, then (P) > . In particular, if is singular, then Q is not σ-centered and all c.c.c. partial orders of cardinality < have a Baire number (1.1) strictly greater than . It was suggested in [Ku1] to try and use Q(T) (1.2), where T is a tree with no ω1-branches, to get models with singular . It is well known that when T is such a tree, the forcing Q(T) is c.c.c. [BMR], ∣Q(T)∣ = ∣T∣, and if T is not special, then n(Q(T)) ≤ ∣T∣.
Abstract. We show that 0(0) implies that there is a first countable < 6-collectionwise Hausdorff space that is not weakly (9-collectionwise Hausdorff. We also show that in the model obtained by Levy collapsing a weakly compact (supercompact) cardinal to a>2, first countable ¡»^-collectionwise Hausdorff spaces are weakly ^-collectionwise Hausdorff (weakly collectionwise Hausdorff). In the last section we show that assuming E% , a certain 0-family of integer-valued functions exists and that in the model obtained by Levy collapsing a supercompact cardinal to u>i . these families do not exist.
Abstract. We show that 0(0) implies that there is a first countable < 6-collectionwise Hausdorff space that is not weakly (9-collectionwise Hausdorff. We also show that in the model obtained by Levy collapsing a weakly compact (supercompact) cardinal to a>2, first countable ¡»^-collectionwise Hausdorff spaces are weakly ^-collectionwise Hausdorff (weakly collectionwise Hausdorff). In the last section we show that assuming E% , a certain 0-family of integer-valued functions exists and that in the model obtained by Levy collapsing a supercompact cardinal to u>i . these families do not exist.
scite is a Brooklyn-based organization that helps researchers better discover and understand research articles through Smart Citations–citations that display the context of the citation and describe whether the article provides supporting or contrasting evidence. scite is used by students and researchers from around the world and is funded in part by the National Science Foundation and the National Institute on Drug Abuse of the National Institutes of Health.
customersupport@researchsolutions.com
10624 S. Eastern Ave., Ste. A-614
Henderson, NV 89052, USA
This site is protected by reCAPTCHA and the Google Privacy Policy and Terms of Service apply.
Copyright © 2024 scite LLC. All rights reserved.
Made with 💙 for researchers
Part of the Research Solutions Family.