Modifying Adjuncts 2003
DOI: 10.1515/9783110894646.67
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Genitives, relational nouns, and argument-modifier ambiguity

Abstract: The argument-modifier distinction is less clear i n NPs than in VPs since nouns do not typically take arguments. The clearest cases of arguments in NPs are found in certain kinds of nominalizations which retain some "verbal" properties (Grimshaw 1990). The status of apparent arguments of non-deverbal relational nouns like sister is more controversial.Genitive constructions like John's teacher, team of John's offer a challenging testing ground for the argument-modifier distinction in NPs, both in English and cr… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

2
48
0
1

Year Published

2005
2005
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
5
4
1

Relationship

0
10

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 60 publications
(51 citation statements)
references
References 18 publications
2
48
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…As pointed out by Partee (1983/1997), Löbner (1985, Jensen and Vikner (1994), Partee and Borschev (2003), Barker (2011), among others, a small set of nouns, denoting family relations (e.g., brother, cousin) and body parts (e.g., head, leg), are properly (or inherently) relational, which means that they involve a relationship between two participants (i.e., are transitive, as opposed to sortal nouns, which have one participant and are intransitive). 15 We are uncertain at this moment about whether such analysis might be extended to Germanic languages such as English, German and Dutch.…”
Section: Lexical Relationshipmentioning
confidence: 90%
“…As pointed out by Partee (1983/1997), Löbner (1985, Jensen and Vikner (1994), Partee and Borschev (2003), Barker (2011), among others, a small set of nouns, denoting family relations (e.g., brother, cousin) and body parts (e.g., head, leg), are properly (or inherently) relational, which means that they involve a relationship between two participants (i.e., are transitive, as opposed to sortal nouns, which have one participant and are intransitive). 15 We are uncertain at this moment about whether such analysis might be extended to Germanic languages such as English, German and Dutch.…”
Section: Lexical Relationshipmentioning
confidence: 90%
“…Von Fintel (1998) -borrowing examples from Westerståhl (1984) and Soames (1986) argues that contextual restrictions on sentences containing quantifiers cannot be reduced to global restrictions of the discourse domain. E.g., there is no way of restricting the 5 It is possible that such variety of "understandings" noted above (in 1) may only appear when one has something greater than a one-place predicate, i.e., quite possibly this phenomenon should only appear with relational terms (Barker (1995), Partee and Borschev (2003)), an interesting question but one we do not take up here. Another related topic we also leave aside is the question of whether the implicit argument structure provided in qualia structures (Pustejovsky, 1995;Vikner and Jensen, 2002) provides a fruitful avenue of exploration.…”
Section: Locality (Take 1)mentioning
confidence: 96%
“…Ils se distinguent en cela des autres types de noms (garçon, livre, maison, chien, etc. ), qui, eux, ne nécessitent pas d'argument (Partee, 2000, Heller, 2002, et pour lesquels la construction possessive n'est que facultative. La présence d'un article défini étant une propriété liée à l'emploi de la construction possessive, l'hypothèse proposée permet d'expliquer les particularités distributionnelles de l'article défini avec les noms abstraits intensifs.…”
Section: Hypothèseunclassified