2017
DOI: 10.33134/eeja.157
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Obligations to Artworks as Duties of Love

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
14
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
6

Relationship

0
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 7 publications
(14 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
14
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Creators can experience a sense of disloyalty or conflict when they violate their artistic integrity (Mills, 2018), and audiences as well as artists can feel as though they have let themselves down in their aesthetic lives (Kubala, 2018; Moran, 2012). Another response might be to model our relationships to artworks along the lines of our relationships to persons, which are famously characterized by conflicting obligations (Cross, 2017a). The strongest response to Nussbaum, however, would be to develop a clearer picture of the aesthetic reactive attitudes and when they are warranted.…”
Section: Six Quick Argumentsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Creators can experience a sense of disloyalty or conflict when they violate their artistic integrity (Mills, 2018), and audiences as well as artists can feel as though they have let themselves down in their aesthetic lives (Kubala, 2018; Moran, 2012). Another response might be to model our relationships to artworks along the lines of our relationships to persons, which are famously characterized by conflicting obligations (Cross, 2017a). The strongest response to Nussbaum, however, would be to develop a clearer picture of the aesthetic reactive attitudes and when they are warranted.…”
Section: Six Quick Argumentsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…81–83. See also Cross, , and Kubala, for more examples of work on the normative importance of personal aesthetic attachments).…”
Section: Objections To Aesthetic Hedonismmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…As a result, this approach, unlike Cross's and Kubala's arguably do, does not suggest that the normative requirements that aesthetic objects appear to place on us can have, at best, the status of a veridical hallucinations. For here aesthetic objects 9 For additional discussion see, e.g., Cross 2017 andKubala 2018. themselves give rise to aesthetic obligations, even if we only realize them in virtue of our recognition and affirmation that we are parts of larger harmonious wholes that include those objects. And while aesthetic obligation may be best seen as involving aesthetic objects themselves, rather than distinctively aesthetic features such as their, e.g., beauty, because we realize aesthetic obligations via the recognition and affirmation of objects', e.g., beauty, aesthetic experience is crucial-if not essential-for realizing them.…”
Section: Oneness and Aesthetic Obligation: An Alternative Approachmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…One cannot, it would seem, owe anything to, or have a demand placed on them by, e.g., a tree or flower, or an inanimate object like a mountain or painted canvas. Hence, in recent years, variations of b) have received more attention: for example, Anthony Cross (Cross ) argues that aesthetic obligation is a species of self‐obligation incurred in virtue of loving some object, and Robbie Kubala (Kubala ) argues that aesthetic obligation is a species of self‐promising. One consequence of these approaches, however, is that they arguably imply that the normative requirements that aesthetic objects appear to place on us can have, at best, the status of veridical hallucinations.…”
Section: A Problem Concerning Aesthetic Obligationmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation