2003
DOI: 10.5840/jphil2003100321
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Qualia and Analytical Conditionals

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1

Citation Types

0
24
0

Year Published

2005
2005
2017
2017

Publication Types

Select...
6
3

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 73 publications
(24 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
24
0
Order By: Relevance
“…
Abstract:The conditional analysis of phenomenal concepts, as proposed independently by Hawthorne (2002), Stalnaker (2002 and Braddon-Mitchell (2003), is used to undermine Chalmers's (1996) conceivability argument in a way that is compatible with our having the zombie intuition. The aim of this paper is twofold: (1) To remove current misconceptions concerning how the analysis is to be applied.
…”
mentioning
confidence: 94%
“…
Abstract:The conditional analysis of phenomenal concepts, as proposed independently by Hawthorne (2002), Stalnaker (2002 and Braddon-Mitchell (2003), is used to undermine Chalmers's (1996) conceivability argument in a way that is compatible with our having the zombie intuition. The aim of this paper is twofold: (1) To remove current misconceptions concerning how the analysis is to be applied.
…”
mentioning
confidence: 94%
“…This is because, if we think of words as individuated in such a fine-grained way, we can still think of doing analysis on the concepts that these words express even if we cannot use the same word to express different concepts. 5 This point is underscored in David Braddon-Mitchell's way of developing Jackson's basic understanding of conceptual analysis in (Braddon-Mitchell 2003). 6 I use the term ''predicate-type'' concept here to signal that Jackson's theory is aimed at concepts such as those expressed by the terms ''dog'' and ''chair'' and not at such things as logical or modal operators.…”
Section: Jackson's Theory Of Conceptual Analysismentioning
confidence: 99%
“…As I see it, Jackson's theory of concepts is important chiefly because it is one of most sophisticated and systematic attempts to articulate an understanding of concepts that is widely accepted in large parts of philosophical practice. In some cases, this acceptance is relatively explicit-e.g., by philosophers such as David Chalmers, Phillip Pettit, David Braddon-Mitchell, and Michael Smith (Chalmers 1996;Pettit 2003;Braddon-Mitchell 2003;Smith 2004). In other cases, the theory of conceptual analysis is largely presupposed but not formally endorsed-e.g., in areas ranging from philosophy of mind to philosophy of law to formal semantics.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Intuitively, they seem conceivable, and many take this to support their metaphysical possibility -a result that, most agree, would refute physicalism. John Hawthorne (2002) [Philosophical Studies 109, 17-52] and David Braddon-Mitchell (2003) [The Journal of Philosophy 100, have developed a novel response to this argument: phenomenal concepts have a conditional structure -they refer to non-physical states if such states exist and otherwise to physical states -and this explains the zombie intuition. I argue that this strategy fails.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%