2005
DOI: 10.1007/s00199-004-0467-7
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The Copeland rule and Condorcet?s principle

Abstract: The purpose of this note is to shed some light on the relationship between the Copeland rule and the Condorcet principle in those cases where there does not exist a Condorcet winner. It will be shown that the Copeland rule ranks alternatives according to their distances to being a Condorcet winner.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

2
6
0
1

Year Published

2006
2006
2015
2015

Publication Types

Select...
5
4

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 21 publications
(9 citation statements)
references
References 17 publications
2
6
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…We have made an extensive discussion of properties with a particular attention to the analysis of societies that are divided into disjoint parts that produce the same collective decision; here and elsewhere we concluded that the Borda benchmark permits a much better aggregative behavior than Copeland. Besides, our model reconciles the measurement of magnitudes of (dis)agreement of preferences with social choice theory in the vein of earlier works like: Kemeny (1959), who proposes a social welfare ordering that maximizes the probability of agreement with a randomly selected member of the group; Baigent (1987), who shows that social welfare functions that verify certain proximity preservation property cannot both respect unanimity and be anonymous (see also Baigent, 1989;Nitzan, 1989;Klamler, 2005) . They argue that cohesiveness should be higher at the following profile P than at P : z P y P x 1 .…”
Section: Related Literature and Concluding Remarkssupporting
confidence: 72%
“…We have made an extensive discussion of properties with a particular attention to the analysis of societies that are divided into disjoint parts that produce the same collective decision; here and elsewhere we concluded that the Borda benchmark permits a much better aggregative behavior than Copeland. Besides, our model reconciles the measurement of magnitudes of (dis)agreement of preferences with social choice theory in the vein of earlier works like: Kemeny (1959), who proposes a social welfare ordering that maximizes the probability of agreement with a randomly selected member of the group; Baigent (1987), who shows that social welfare functions that verify certain proximity preservation property cannot both respect unanimity and be anonymous (see also Baigent, 1989;Nitzan, 1989;Klamler, 2005) . They argue that cohesiveness should be higher at the following profile P than at P : z P y P x 1 .…”
Section: Related Literature and Concluding Remarkssupporting
confidence: 72%
“…To date, the most complete list of distance-rationalizable rules is provided by Meskanen and Nurmi (2008) (but see also Baigent (1987); Klamler (2005bKlamler ( , 2005a). There, the authors show how to distance-rationalize many voting rules, including, among others, Plurality, Borda, Veto, Copeland, Dodgson, Kemeny, Slater, and STV.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This closeness must be measured by a distance function since violations of the triangle inequality may lead to undesirable effects. These ideas has been explored by several authors (Baigent, 1987;Klamler, 2005bKlamler, , 2005a) under a variety of names; a fairly comprehensive list of distance-rationalizability results is provided by Meskanen and Nurmi (2008).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%