2014
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-014-0335-7
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

This paper surely contains some errors

Abstract: The preface paradox can be motivated by appealing to a plausible inference from an author's reasonable assertion that her book is bound to contain errors to the author's rational belief that her book contains errors. By evaluating and undermining the validity of this inference, I offer a resolution of the paradox. Discussions of the preface paradox have surprisingly failed to note that expressions of fallibility made in prefaces typically employ terms such as surely, undoubtedly, and bound to be. After conside… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2016
2016
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
4

Relationship

1
3

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 4 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 34 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…10 Makinson [1965], Klein [1985], Foley [1993], and Christensen [2004] all reject a version of PP1. Pollock [1990], Ryan [1991], Kaplan [1996], Adler [2002], and Kim [2015] all reject versions of PP2, PP3, or their conjunction. Finally, Schechter [2013] argues that the real problem behind the preface paradox, a problem with the deductive closure of justification, re-appears even after the probabilistic resolution discussed above.…”
Section: Non-cummulative Inductive Basesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…10 Makinson [1965], Klein [1985], Foley [1993], and Christensen [2004] all reject a version of PP1. Pollock [1990], Ryan [1991], Kaplan [1996], Adler [2002], and Kim [2015] all reject versions of PP2, PP3, or their conjunction. Finally, Schechter [2013] argues that the real problem behind the preface paradox, a problem with the deductive closure of justification, re-appears even after the probabilistic resolution discussed above.…”
Section: Non-cummulative Inductive Basesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Alternatively, those sympathetic to closure have the option of rejecting (P3) instead. Advocates of this latter strategy include Pollock (1986), Ryan (1991), Leplin (2009), Kaplan (2013), Kim (2015), and Smith (2016). Arguments for rejecting (P3) typically pivot on the idea that the author's mere recognition of her own fallibility is not sufficient to justify the belief that her book will contain any errors.…”
Section: The Preface Paradoxmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In the preface paradox, it is effectively left open what kind of evidence I have for believing each of P 1 , P 2 , … , P 100 , allowing us to fill in the details as we see fit, but the evidence I have for believing ̃P 1 ∨̃P 2 ∨ … ∨̃P 100 is fixed-it consists in the fact that I am fallible and that comparably ambitious books have always turned out to contain falsehoods. By denying that belief can be justified on the basis of this 'pessimistic inductive' evidence, one can avoid the paradox and preserve Closure (see, for instance, Ryan 1991;Kaplan 2013;Kim 2015;Smith 2016, section 4.1).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%